We're delighted to pass along this post from Yale's Daniel Markovits concerning his new book, A Modern Legal Ethics: Adversary Advocacy in a Democratic Age:
Thanks to Andrew Perlman and the other editors of the Legal
Ethics Forum for giving me this chance to say something about my new book, A Modern Legal Ethics: Adversary Advocacy in a Democratic Age. It’s a treat to have a chance to write
directly to this audience and in this forum.
Begin with politics. The signal achievement of the last generation of (especially philosophical) scholarship in legal ethics has been to bring moral philosophy to bear on lawyers’ professional conduct in a serious way. Sophisticated moral argument shows that lawyers’ ordinary moral personalities shine through their professional roles, so that the ordinary moral obligations that all persons have to pursue what is right and true cannot be eclipsed by either role-ethics or the simple division of labor arguments associated with the classical adversary system excuse. Serious moral analysis therefore almost invariably concludes that lawyers may display much less aggressive partisanship than conventional accounts of adversary advocacy recommend. The formal attributes of the lawyer’s role cannot plausibly offer the resistance to ordinary moral evaluation that conventional accounts of the lawyer’s role morality propose.
The scope of lawyers’ political duties, and their relationship to traditional conceptions of lawyerly partisanship and fidelity to clients, is an open question. Some contemporary legal ethicists – most notably Brad Wendel – think that lawyers’ political function requires them to be true to the law rather than to clients. I believe – as I argue in the book – that lawyers can contribute to political legitimacy only if they pursue a much more traditional client-centered and partisan professional self-conception. The difference between these positions turns on deep and complex questions concerning the nature of political legitimacy. In particular it turns on whether (as Wendel believes) democratic law-making can carry the burden of legitimating political power on its own or whether it must instead (as I believe) be supplemented by a practice of law-application, or adjudication, constructed to serve as a separate, free-standing legitimating force. I explain why I find the second approach persuasive in the book, but that is in a way beside the point. I am much less confident in the particular manner in which I embed legal ethics in politics than in the general proposition that an adequate account of legal ethics must take politics much more seriously than the familiar views do. And taking politics seriously cannot avoid having substantial implications for lawyers’ first-order professional duties.
Although the political emphasis of these arguments is novel, the general style of the argument – namely, the construction of an impersonal, external evaluation of lawyers’ practical lives – should be familiar to legal ethicists. The book’s second central preoccupation departs dramatically from such external accounts to address the inner ethical lives of lawyers. I observe that the positive law, both in its doctrinal details and in its genetic code (arising out of the structural separation between advocate and tribunal), requires lawyers to display professional vices that have familiar names: specifically, that it requires them to betray their personal judgments of truth in a manner that amounts to lying and to betray their personal sense of fairness in a manner that amounts to cheating. I then ask what it is like – not psychologically but ethically – to live subject to the professional duties of self-effacement (or negative capability, as I call it) that govern lawyers’ professional lives and to the vices that these duties call on lawyers to display. I argue that this self-effacement threatens lawyers’ integrity, and I develop a philosophically articulate account of the nature of integrity and of the proper place for considerations of integrity in all-things-considered practical deliberations. Finally, I propose a renovation of role-morality, reconstructed as a complement rather than a substitute for ordinary moral argument. I claim that even though philosophical legal ethicists are rightly dismissive of suggestions that role morality can insulate lawyers from the moral requirements that are common to universal humanity, role can help lawyers who satisfy these requirements to sustain their integrity in circumstances in which ordinary morality places their integrity under threat.
The details of these arguments may be found in the book, but my principal purpose here is once again to recast the problem of legal ethics rather than to promote my own peculiar solution to it. And I am again more confident that an adequate philosophical reconstruction of lawyers’ ethical lives must take into account their own perspectives on the tensions that their professional obligations produce in them than I am that the particular diagnoses of these tensions – involving integrity and its philosophical concomitants – that I elaborate in the book are correct.
The book’s third innovation is
methodological rather than substantive but not, I think, any less important for
this emphasis. Most legal ethics, and indeed most applied ethics more
generally, tends towards casuistry: it begins by identifying general principles
of value and right action and then applies these principles to a particular set
of facts in order to generate prescriptions about what should be done. I am dubious of this approach. To begin with, the general principles from
which casuistic arguments in applied ethics begin tend to be too simplistic,
and the facts to which the arguments apply these principles tend to be too
stylized, for the casuistry to be persuasive. Moreover, it is probably not
realistic to expect philosophy to have such mechanical and immediate regulative
implications for ethical life as casuistry supposes. Ethics – at least in the sense of living well
– simply is not a technical subject in the way casuistry presumes but instead
involves complexities and offers possibilities for practical and indeed ethical
creativity and judgment that casuistic approaches to applied ethics cannot
encompass.
This is not to claim (which would be absurd) that philosophy is irrelevant to ethics. But although philosophers, and characteristically philosophical forms of thought, do have distinctive contributions to make to ethical life, their contributions are primarily interpretive and reconstructive rather than directly regulative. The task of philosophical ethics is therefore primarily to elaborate what is rather than to command what should be. Of course, a philosophical advance in understanding a form of ethical life may lead to changes in that form of life, as participants and indeed outsiders adjust their engagements with that form of life in light of how they have come to understand it. But the choices involved in actually making these adjustments have an independent ethical content of their own, involving ethical creativity and judgment. They are not entailed by any direct application of philosophical understanding to ethical life.
Whereas almost all traditional philosophical legal ethics employs one or another form of casuistry, the questions I set myself in the book accept this account of the limits and possibilities of philosophical ethics: I abandon casuistry entirely in favor of interpretive reconstruction. Thus, instead of evaluating the positive law with a direct eye to reform, I take the basic outlines of adversary advocacy for granted and embark on a detailed interpretive engagement with doctrine in order to elaborate the legal, ethical, and political values and forms of life are immanent in this professional regime. (This, by the way, makes the book useful for teaching the positive law.)
Moreover, this commitment in favor of interpretive over regulative approaches to applied ethics works itself inward in the book’s argument, into the details of its engagement with the positive practice of adversary lawyering. Most immediately, I resist the temptation to focus discussions of legal ethics on extraordinary cases – for example, cases in which lawyers present an alibi defense that they know to be false, keep a life-threatening secret, intimidate an adverse party by investigating her sexual history, or even bring a false murder prosecution – preferring instead to emphasize the ethical questions that arise in adversary legal practice quite generally, in the banal conduct of lawyers’ workaday professional lives. Sensational cases may be suited to casuistry, because they usefully support intuitive tests of the limits of justified partisanship. But exceptional cases are much less useful for elaborating a philosophical reconstruction of the constant core of adversary advocacy rather for fixing its variable boundaries. In order to know what a practice is really like, it is better to ask what it is ordinarily like rather than to fixate on what it becomes as it starts cracking under pressure. Sensational cases, which are the main-stays of most discussions of legal ethics, are attention-grabbing, to be sure. But it is a mistake to emphasize them: just as great cases make bad law, so they make bad legal ethics.